Radical media, politics and culture.

Bruno Gulli, "Time and Labor in the <i>Grundirsse</i>

"The Labor of Fire:
On Time and Labor in the Grundrisse"

Bruno Gulli, Found Object

Labor is the living, form-giving fire; it is the transitoriness of things, their temporality, as their formation by living time. — Marx, Grundrisse

1. The Thisness of Time and Production

The Grundrisse is a work about time, and it is so in a fundamental sense. This means that time is the most fundamental category of the Grundrisse. Again, it means that time is the subject of Marx’s critique of political economy–subject in the double sense of subject-matter (or object) and of ground (or foundation). This becomes evident as soon as one opens the Grundrisse : "The object before us, to begin with, material production" (Marx 1973, 83). This is how Notebook M starts.

But material production is time, both as objectified and as subjective labor. The tense of this time, which is immediately labor, is alternatively the perfect or present tense: "The difference between previous, objectified labor and living, present labor here [i.e., in the accumulation of capital] appears as a merely formal difference between the different tenses of labor, at one time in the perfect and at another in the present" (465-466; brackets added). Material production is, then, time both as having been produced and as producing, as having become and as becoming. The difference between these two modalities is the difference between the substantial form of capital and living labor, between the capitalist and the worker. It is a difference, which presents itself immediately as antagonism and opposition. It is, in fact, the structural constitution of the class struggle.But Marx also says: "Economy of time, to this all economy ultimately reduces itself" (173). This means, again, that time is the irreducible subject of political economy as a science as well as of the critique of political economy. But time, as being is also the subject of metaphysics. And if time itself, as Kant says, does not change while everything else changes in time,1 — if, in other words, time remains (in substance) identical with itself — yet, at the same time and in a certain respect, it changes, for this time is different from that time, and there is no time over and beyond each this of its individuation. This means that each moment contracts all time within itself, and that the present — as Benjamin stressed — is always in transition.2

In terms of what Marx says in the Grundrisse, this means that, even though each mode of production is precisely only a mode, the individuating modality is not simply an external addition. If all time is contracted in this moment and all production in this mode of production, the modality itself, far from being extrinsic and general, is essential and singular.

The problem of production is then the problem of time, for production is time. Now, it is as absurd to speak of time in general as it is to speak of production in general. "Whenever we speak of production, then, what is meant is always production at a definite stage of social development–production by social individuals" (Marx 1973, 85). The principium individuationis is here stated in all its meaningfulness. There is no production beyond the this of production. "Production is always a particular branch of production...or it is a totality" (86). Whether it is considered in its particularity or in its totality, production is a concrete whole, and this is what material production stands for: a sort of Aristotelian composite of matter (material) and form (production). Of course, "production in general" can be used as a "rational abstraction," for — as Marx says — "it really brings out and fixes the common element [of all production] and thus saves us repetition" (85; brackets and emphasis added). But that it saves us repetition does not mean that production in general or general production is actually found as either a concrete or abstract reality. As an abstraction, it is only rational, i.e., purely formal and empty. It is not the determinate abstraction (cf. Negri 1991a, 47) Marx will speak about when he deals with abstract labor or with the question of method.

In fact, in these latter two cases — of which more will be said later — the abstraction is still historically determined and it fully and exclusively belongs to the capitalist mode of production. But this is not the case with production in general or general production, where it is not yet a question of "the relationship between scientific presentation [Darstellung] and the real movement" (Marx 1973, 86). Indeed, the aim of those economists who start with general production (with "the general preconditions of all production") is in actuality "to present production...as distinct from distribution etc., as encased in eternal natural laws independent of history, at which opportunity bourgeois relations are then quietly smuggled in as the inviolable natural laws on which society in the abstract is founded"(87). An eminently political aim.

It is very important not to confuse the empty, merely formal and rational abstraction, which may nonetheless have a certain usefulness in discourse and method, with the determinate abstraction which has a massive socio-ontological status of its own. In other words, it is important not to confuse the empty formula of the thing with the thing’s actual structure and power, the level of predication with that of reality.

All of the above does not cancel the truth that "all epochs of production have certain common traits, common characteristics [Bestimmungen]" (85; brackets and emphasis added). This commonality is certainly very important. However, even more important are the different determinations, the essential difference, without which a mode of production would not be this mode. Indeed, the word "mode" in the expression "mode of production" is fundamental. If one spoke about production in general, one would be speaking about a what without knowing which what it was, without knowing the how of the what. That would amount to speaking about something very indefinite and vague. Furthermore, the how that constitutes a what as this what is not an accidental one. Rather, it is essential. Yet, by being essential, it is not eternal, immutable, and common. It is essential, and yet it is a difference. It is, in fact, an essential difference: "...the elements which are not general and common, must be separated out from the determinations valid for production as such, so that in their unity — which arises already from the identity of the subject, humanity, and of the object, nature — their essential difference is not forgotten" (85; emphasis added).

The importance of distinguishing between the essential difference and the common element of production cannot be stressed enough. In fact, by confusing the two, bourgeois political economy is able to prove, logically, that capital is a necessary and common element of production. The syllogism of political economy is as follows: Since no production is possible without an instrument of production or past labor and since capital is also an instrument of production and past labor, then capital is "a general, eternal relation of nature" (85–86). Of course, Marx adds, "that is, if I leave out just the specific quality which alone makes ‘instrument of production’ and ‘stored-up labor’ into ‘capital’" (86; emphasis added).3 The logic of bourgeois political economy makes capital into a common element of all modes of production because it does not isolate the specific determinations from the common determinations of production. Both kinds of determinations are essential, but they are not essential in the same way. Of course, all epochs have both specific and common determinations, but whereas the latter are always the same, the former are each time different. That the specific determinations are also essential only means that production is not conceivable without a mode of production. That they are different means that this mode always changes (and yet a mode must be there). The capitalist mode of production is not production proper, i.e., production as immediate subjective creation, though the concept of production proper is subsumed within it. Fundamentally, the capitalist mode of production requires the conversion of use value into exchange value, the reduction of the labor capacity to a commodity, and the creation of surplus value.

On the other hand, the common element of production is nothing but the "already" of "the identity of the subject, humanity, and of the object, nature" (85), namely, living labor. However, in the already of this identity, living labor is always useful labor.4 It is, of course, time, but time as quality not as quantity. With the coming of a commodity economy — and particularly with capital — living labor is split into two different aspects or properties: useful (or concrete) and abstract labor — "different in their very essence" (Marx 1977, 309). Abstract labor, which at first could seem as the common element, is, in reality, a specific quality of the logic of exchange value.5 In fact, abstract labor is the creator of value, which is the substance of exchange value and thus of money. However, this does not mean that abstract labor is a pure invention of capital. Rather, it is that aspect of living labor which capital is able to isolate and extract, to reproduce, and be produced by.6 The implication is not that abstract labor is in complete opposition to useful labor. In fact, there can be no expenditure of the former without expenditure of the latter. Thus, even though capital’s only interest is time as quantity, it cannot avoid the quality of time as a plurality of subjective practices.

Remark 1: Dialectic and Metaphysics

A. To speak about time is, in general, to speak about metaphysics or ontology. Now, this can seem strange, for Marx is certainly an anti-metaphysical thinker. Indeed, insofar as Marx’s philosophy is based on dialectic, it is an anti-metaphysical philosophy. In fact, dialectical thinking represents one of the ways in which western philosophy has tried to overcome or get rid of metaphysics. Hence, dialectic and metaphysics have often been contrasted as opposite. The opposition between dialectic and metaphysics can be reduced to the opposition — within presocratic philosophy — between Heraclitus and Parmenides. Supposedly, the former says that everything constantly changes, everything is in flux; the latter that nothing ever changes, that everything remains the same. The former presents a philosophy of becoming; the latter a philosophy of permanence. However, this view is not necessarily correct. Both Hegel and Heidegger have shown the fundamental agreement between the philosophies of Heraclitus and Parmenides. Moreover, reality itself shows–as soon as one thinks a little about it–that becoming and permanence cannot be in a position of mutual exclusion, but rather that the one cannot be without the other. The correct view would then be that things change and yet do not change. In other words, they change in certain respects and do not change in others.7

B. The question of dialectic raises the question of the relation of Marx to Hegel, as well as the question of the relation of the Grundrisse to Capital. According to Negri (1991a), these questions are resolved by denying anything which is more than a terminological and conceptual resemblance between Hegel and Marx and by establishing the Grundrisse as autonomous from Capital. For Negri, the Grundrisse is not a rough draft to be used for philological purposes, but a political text in its own right. Indeed, the Grundrisse is for him superior to Capital, for the openness of the former makes possible what the objectified categories of the latter impede: the action by revolutionary subjectivity (8-9).8 At the end of his book, Negri denies the dialectic, "that eternal formula of Judeo-Christian thought, that circumlocution for saying–in the Western world–rationality" (189).

Rosdolsky, on the other hand and before Negri, sees what he constantly calls the Rough Draft as "a massive reference to Hegel, in particular to his Logic" (1977, xiii) and considers superficial the view that Marx’s relation to Hegel is only terminological and external. Furthermore, as the title of his book explicitly says, the Grundrisse is for Rosdolsky a preparation to Capital. However, he warns that one "should not...exaggerate the similarity of the two works" (51). And pointing to the transformation of money into capital as an important moment of this similarity, he concludes: "Both are the product of Marx’s dialectical method... The difference lies only in the method of presentation" (189–190; emphasis added).

It is evident that the views of Rosdolsky and Negri are diametrically opposed, yet their opposition does not require that readers of the Grundrisse or of Marx in general take sides with either one or the other. As Rosdolsky’s reference to Schumpeter shows,9 his interpretation tends toward an appraisal of the dialectic against a background, which seems to reduce the hermeneutical options to either metaphysics10 or positive science. Rosdolsky’s further references, to Lenin and Lukács, make it clear that the question of the dialectic and of its passage from Hegel to Marx — notwithstanding the latter’s radical and materialist inversion of it — has to remain central within Marxism, against both vulgar metaphysics and its offspring, positivism. "The publication of the Grundrisse means that academic critics of Marx will no longer be able to write without first having studied his method and its relation to Hegel" (Rosdolsky, 1977, xiii).

Negri, however, starts from different theoretical and practical premises. His reading, which stems out of the experience of the Autonomy Movement in Italy and is in accordance with the Althusserian and Deleuzian destruction of Hegelianism, is also an attack against the orthodoxy of Marxism and of the traditional communist party. Furthermore, by abandoning the dialectic, Negri is not concerned with the question as to whether Marxism is a metaphysics or a positive science. He has, in fact — at the time of Marx Beyond Marx and subsequently — a different conception of metaphysics, namely, metaphysics as an antagonistic and alternative political ontology, or constitutive practice, which seems to have little or no use of the categories of the traditional dialectic. In this sense, the dialectic also falls within the vulgar metaphysics it tried to combat.

The question of the relation of the Grundrisse to Capital and of Marx to Hegel becomes a hermeneutical and a political question. Of course, hermeneutics itself is always political, yet it is not so in a dogmatic way. I cannot elaborate on this problem here, but I will try to present a few suggestions. It is, I believe, fair to say that Rosdolsky’s view is hermeneutically correct insofar as it considers the dialectic as intrinsic to the real movement and to the mode of presentation in the Grundrisse. In this sense, it is also fair to say that the Grundrisse can illuminate the reading of Capital. However, it is also important to recognize the openness of Marx’s dialectic against the circularity of the dialectic of Hegel. Hegel goes to pieces when the form of capital proves to be unable to return to itself, when what seemed to be a circle turns out to be a spiral. "Exchange value posited as the unity of commodity and money is Capital, and this positing itself appears as the circulation of capital. (Which is, however, a spiral, an expanding curve, not a simple circle)" (Marx 1973, 266; emphasis added). But circularity is, for Hegel, the essential requirement of dialectical logic: "The essential requirement for the science of logic is...that the whole of the science be within itself a circle in which the first is also the last and the last is also the first" (Hegel 1989, 71). Like Nietzsche’s Zarathustra to the dwarf who said that "time itself is a circle," Marx is saying to an ideal Hegel (for instance, to Proudhon): "do not make things too easy for yourself!" (Nietzsche 1954, 270). However, the spiral movement is not a denial of the dialectic; it is rather a denial of the circularity which lies more in the movement of the concept than in the real movement.11

Indeed, the dialectic still remains as the motor of a movement, which breaks free of the circle into a spiral. At this point, the question must be posed as to why the dialectic is unable to perform the circular movement prescribed by Hegel and why what was supposed to be the end and coincide with the beginning is displaced and thrown into the open.


The answer to the above questions is to be looked for in the concepts and in the reality of crisis and catastrophe.12 The dialectic is broken because reality is broken. The former remains open because openness characterizes the real movement. Thus, politically, Negri’s reading of the Grundrisse is very convincing even though I do not see the reason for denying the dialectic tout court.13

Remark 2: Vulgar Metaphysics and Poetic Metaphysics

In the history of philosophy, it is possible to distinguish between a metaphysics of transcendence — but not of the transcendental — and a metaphysics of immanence. The former can also be called vulgar metaphysics. Its main tenet is the principle of "the ontotheological One" (Alliez 1996, 200). The latter is a poetic metaphysics whose presupposition and result are ethical, practical and whose inner motor is political to the core. Marx’s metaphysics of time is of the latter type, and it is, as Negri says, a "cursed" metaphysics (Negri 1992, 151). It is a cursed metaphysics because it is a materialist one, and because it carries within its womb the tools for a radical transformation of the world.

Critical metaphysics, which starts with Kant, still falls within a vulgar type of metaphysics, even though, by denying access to the thing-in-itself, it keeps reason from deluding itself. But to criticize vulgar — in Kant’s case: dogmatic — metaphysics without building a metaphysics of immanence is tantamount to remaining caught within it. This is also the case with Heidegger, the school of deconstruction, and analytic philosophy in general. It is not the case with Nietzsche and Marx.

It is true that today one cannot overlook Heidegger’s fundamental contribution to the question of time. Yet, as Negri says, one does not need to compare Marx to Heidegger in order to understand the former’s concept of time. In fact, "Marx has a metaphysics of time as, indeed, more radical than Heidegger’s" (Negri 1992, 41). With Marx, "...temporality can be rooted in man’s productive capacity, in the ontology of his becoming — an open temporality, absolutely constitutive, which does not reveal Being but produces beings" (Ibid.).

The difference between "revealing" and "producing" is fundamental. The Heideggerian modality of revealing (and this is also true of the later Heidegger on language and technology) still retains something of the beyond typical of vulgar metaphysics.14 For Marx, on the other hand, the metaphysics of time does not reveal anything. If there is a hidden subject, it affirms itself in and through production. If there is a subterranean fire, it breaks itself open through its incessant labor. Negri continues: "...Marx liberates what Heidegger ties up; Marx lights up with praxis what Heidegger brings back to the mystical. The Heideggerian time is the form of Being, it is the indistinction of an absolute ground; the Marxian time is production of being, it is still a form, but the form of an absolute procedure. The Marxian temporality is the key through which a subject which is formally predisposed to the adequation with an absolute procedure becomes materially able to enter such a process, to define itself as constituent power" (42).15 The substance of this constituent power is time. Marx’s metaphysics of time is the open dialectic of living labor "set free" by the inability of capital to reconstitute its own identity.

Identical is only that concept which, without being a one, is contracted into an infinite series of possible differences. In the history of western metaphysics, this concept has been established by John Duns Scotus in an objective fashion. This means that the concept is not an empty abstraction but a real, objective being. The self-identity of this concept, namely, its neutral immediacy, which is also absolute difference, allows for its univocal expansion and inclusion into everything that is.16 This concept can be given different names: being, time, power (as potentia, i.e., not as constituted but as constituent power).17

It is the principle of that which can be and not be, which is and is not. In Marxian terms, moving from pure ontology to political ontology, this concept is living labor. It is then the principle which demystifies the view of bourgeois philosophy and political economy according to which the laws governing the capitalist mode of production are immutable and eternal. In fact, the capitalist mode of production is this repetition of an ongoing process, which is the process of becoming itself. It is this essential difference that, as long as it is, totalizes itself and works toward the subsumption of everything else under itself. But precisely by so doing, precisely by this act of subsuming and totalizing, of turning itself into a positive whole, of leaving nothing outside itself, it reaches its concept and vanishes and withers away. The concept of the end, so much talked about in these recent years, is nothing but the coming to completion of an essential difference. It is true that this essential difference (the capitalist mode of production) is such that it has subsumed everything under itself and has left (actually: created) nothing outside.

Yet it would be useful to ask, in a Heideggerian fashion: is this nothing really nothing or is it something after all? The answer is that the nothing which lies outside the positive whole in which our essential difference has transformed itself is time as the constituent power of being, time which either becomes completely subsumed under capital and constitutes the substance of the latter’s valorization or exceeds the capacity of capital and is seen by the latter as waste time.18 If it is nothing, that is only because capital has no use for it. Capital has in fact already become, it has accomplished — through the appropriation without exchange of one part of its own negation: surplus labor — its M-M’ movement, it has tried to rejoin itself a step ahead of itself. Yet this nothing — which is capital’s own creation — is caught within the spiral movement of capital as the force that breaks the circle open into a spiral, for, in its constant drive to go beyond itself, to expand and yet desperately try to maintain a stable identity, capital steps into the very nothing it needs to use or disregard (cf. Negri 1991a, 91 and 100; and Marx 1973, 462).19 Yet capital cannot avoid stepping outside itself, for this movement belongs to its concept. The nothing outside capital, the not-capital is labor, living labor, regardless of whether it is productive (i.e., actually employed by capital for its own valorization) or not. I will return to this point below.

2. The Problem of Method

In "The Method of Political Economy," Marx deals with the relationship between the method of presentation and the real movement. He says "the method of raising from the abstract to the concrete is only the way in which thought appropriates the concrete, reproduces it as the concrete in the mind. But this is by no means the process by which the concrete itself comes into being" (1973, 101).


One will not be able to think the concrete as concrete if one does not grasp its elemental structure. And one cannot grasp the latter on the basis of Vorstellung, representation. In thought, the concrete comes at the end of a process of analysis and synthesis, though in reality it comes at the beginning. In the process of thinking, the concrete appears "as a result, not as a point of departure, even though it is the point of departure in reality and hence also the point of departure for observation [Anschauung] and conception" (101). If thought stops at the level of concretion, it will only reach a confused representation of reality and an abstraction; the latter, however, will not be a meaningful, determinate abstraction, but an empty one.


Of course, Marx’s abstraction is not the empty abstraction of the logician, but it is a determinate abstraction, i.e., "the abstraction which seeks the real in the concrete" (Negri 1991a, 48).20 It is the internal structure of the concrete divided into its constitutive elements: division of labor, money, value, commodity, etc. Ascending from these abstractions to the concrete makes it possible for the latter to be reconstituted in thought as it really is: a "concentration of many determinations," a "unity of the diverse" (Marx 1973, 101), without having the obscurity and confusion of representational, pictorial thinking. As Marx himself says, making the example of labor, "even the most abstract categories, despite their validity — precisely because of their abstractness — for all epochs, are nevertheless, in the specific character of this abstraction, themselves likewise a product of historic relations, and possess their full validity only for and within these relations" (105). Which means that these abstractions are not timeless, but always rooted in time and in history.

The method that goes from the abstract to the concrete is the one which takes into consideration the common element of production and the specificity of each mode of production. The common element is not something determined a priori, on the basis of thinking alone: "As a rule, the most general abstractions arise only in the midst of the richest possible concrete development, where one thing appears as common to many, to all" (104). However, the most important determination is not the common element — with which, however, one needs to start — but the specificity of production: "In all forms of society there is one specific kind of production which predominates over the rest, whose relations thus assign rank and influence to the others" (106–107). Marx continues with a poetic metaphor full of philosophical significance: "It is a general illumination which bathes all the other colours and modifies their particularity. It is a particular ether which determines the specific gravity of every being which has materialized within it" (107). Then, in a way that brings to mind the unpublished chapter of Capital on the formal and real subsumption, Marx says: "Capital is the all-dominating economic power of bourgeois society" (Ibid.)21 The concept of capital is not, as it was for political economy, an abstraction of commonality and a general relation of nature, but it is the most fundamental of the categories "which make up the inner structure of bourgeois society" (108). At this level of analysis — as well as in reality — another fundamental category — one without which capital would not be capital — is wage labor. The end of this process of analysis, which brings to the reconstitution of the concrete in its totality and specificity, is the world market and the crisis of capital. The concept of crisis, however, is one that runs throughout the whole development of capital, and it becomes the concept of the class struggle or — as far as capital is concerned — of the history of bourgeois society. It is the concept of time itself, for, under capital, time is the time of crisis.

3. Money

The time of capital is the time of crisis. It is the difference between M and M’. This difference is a constitutive and thus a positive one. It is in fact the process of realization of capital and the condition of its development.22 But that which constitutes it, living labor, is the negation of that which is constituted by it, capital. Living labor constitutes itself as its own negation: "It posits itself objectively, but it posits this, its objectivity, as its own not-being or as the being of its not-being–of capital" (Marx 1973, 454).


The time of difference is that which changes becoming into a having become.23 The latter moment is not simply the end of the process, but it is also the beginning of a new process. It is a repetition, but one which — in the process of realization — occurs in a time of difference. Money is the subject of this time: a subject which does not have a reality of its own. In fact, money is only the form of value, whose reality, or substance, is labor time which "exists only subjectively, only in the form of activity" (171).

In this sense, labor, as the time of expenditure of its power, is the real subject. Yet, under capital, living labor is expended only if alienated by the worker to the capitalist in an act of free exchange whose vanishing mediation is money.24 Living labor is then wage labor. This means that money, in one of its various functions, appears as the link between the subjectivity of becoming, of living labor, and its objectification into a having become. But money is only the form of appearance of exchange value. Thus, the Grundrisse, in its aspect of being a huge pamphlet against Darimon and the Proudonians, has as its main objective the necessity of abolishing not simply money but exchange value, i.e., the specificity of the capitalist mode of production: "...it is impossible to abolish money itself as long as exchange value remains the social form of product" (145).

Yet the having become of becoming is not fully capital if and until money has not changed into more money. In fact, the dialectic between becoming and having become is not proper of capital, but it belongs to the already of the identity of human beings and nature (85). This is why the concept of subsumption becomes fundamental. If money becomes the form of being25 and being is time, money’s transition to capital is accomplished by subsuming the whole being of the worker — through the appropriation without exchange of a portion of the labor time and the reduction of the other portion to a "consumption fund" (594) for the satisfaction of needs. However, even though the opposition between labor and capital becomes explicit only in a developed form of production (i.e., with the production of surplus value), it is already, though latently, contained in the "simple forms of exchange value and of money" (248), that is to say, in the commodity form.

4. The Form of the Thing

In section one of "The Chapter on Capital" of the Grundrisse

Let me start with the concept of capital. The first thing I want to say is that capital is labor and yet it is not labor. It is not labor, for labor is the not-capital: "the real not-capital is labor" (274). What is meant here by labor is living labor, labor as subjectivity, activity, as the "form-giving fire" (361), which economically and philosophically constitutes a much more general, universal and fundamental category than capital. Capital, in fact, only pertains to the capitalist mode of production, but it pertains to it in an essential way, as its essential difference or specificity. Living labor, on the other hand, pertains to production as such; it is a common element of production. I am not talking here of productive or valorizing labor, which is the form in which labor is subsumed under capital, but of living labor as — I repeat — the fire which gives form to all beings that come out of the relationship between humans and nature or humans and technology. This living labor is, perhaps at times only as possibility, the horizon of capital. Even though capital tries–out of a necessity inherent in its concept–to subsume all labor under itself, living labor always and potentially exceeds the capacity of capital, and this is why a revolution is possible. The necessity inherent in the concept of capital is that which leads capital to employ and not employ as much living labor as it can; it is, in other words, the fundamental contradiction of capital which manifests itself in a special way in the law of the tendency of the rate of profit to decline.26

It is also true that, however, capital is labor. But as such, it is only accumulated, objectified, dead labor. In this sense, capital is understood as a thing, not as a relation or process (258), and in so doing, the most important aspect of capital is lost. To say that capital is accumulated labor — Marx argues against Adam Smith — is to refer to "the simple material of capital, without regard to the formal character without which it is not capital" (257). Marx’s argument here repeats what he has already said in the introduction when he was speaking of the difference between the element common to all production and the essential difference of each mode of production (85-86).27

Since capital is an essential difference and not a common element, it cannot be understood simply as labor. However, this is not only true from the point of view of the most general abstraction, namely, the point of view which abstracts what is common out of the concrete and thus points to what in the concrete is essentially different. As I have noted, capital is not labor because labor is the not-capital. The labor which is objectified as capital (in the means of production, for instance) needs to be resurrected from the dead by living labor (364). Furthermore, capital cannot be a thing because what characterizes it–insofar as it is the representative of money as the general form of wealth–is "the constant drive to go beyond its quantitative limit" (270; see also 334). However, as I have already noted, this drive also constitutes the source of capital’s main contradiction, one which leads it into crises.

What this tells us is that capital is nothing but time (not time in general, not time as time, but a specific modality of time) striving continuously to go beyond itself. It is the time of production as the time of exploitation, the time of total subsumption; it is the urge to make value out of value, surplus value and profit.

It is because capital is not labor, or not labor as labor, that Marx says: "To develop the concept of capital it is necessary to begin not with labor but with value, and precisely, with exchange value in an already developed movement of circulation" (259). In fact, labor as such, not productive or valorizing labor, is, in the last analysis,–i.e., notwithstanding the fact that labor is always socially determined–a relation of nature. As Marx says in Capital, "[l]abour is, first of all, a process between man and nature, a process by which man, through his own actions, mediates, regulates and controls the metabolism between himself and nature" (I, 283). But capital, on the other hand, is an exclusively social category. To go back to the Grundrisse, Marx adds: "It is just as impossible to make the transition directly from labor to capital as it is to go from the different human races directly to the banker, or from nature to the steam engine" (259).

Thus the beginning is made with value, exchange value. But what is value? Exchange value, "the substance of money" (221), is nothing but a given amount of labor time contained in a commodity. The substance of value is labor, but the form of appearance of this substance is exchange value and money. However, from the point of view of the genesis of capital, money is to be considered as the medium of circulation and at the same time, and in addition to that, as what suspends itself from circulation. In this sense, money is and is not in circulation, and this constitutes its transition to capital. The full form of capital — as productive capital — is M-M’. However, the form of circulation M-C-C-M (which presupposes the simple form C-M-M-C) is the first appearance of capital, precisely, of commercial capital. "As soon as money is posited as an exchange value which not only becomes independent of circulation, but which also maintains itself through it, then it is no longer money,...but is capital" (259).29

As we have seen, capital is not a thing but a process. This is so because money as capital is not a thing but a process. Even though the concept of capital cannot be developed from labor, it is labor which remains the substance of things and which also gives form to things. Even the transition from thing to process is something accomplished by labor. In fact, when money returns to itself from circulation and becomes capital (a return which can be seen as a broken identity), labor also returns to itself. "But the nature of the return is this, that the labor objectified in the exchange value posits living labor as a means of reproducing it, whereas, originally, exchange value appeared merely as a product of labor" (263).

What is clearly indicated here is the passage from value to surplus value, for living labor will be necessary and surplus labor. The return is a violent attempt at attaining an impossible identity, and it is in reality not a return, for M has become M’. But what is M-M’? In the words of Éric Alliez: "It is the convulsive movement of what does not come back to itself, the specter of what does not come back into itself, thereby breaking the natural motion of need that had bodied forth in the notion of reciprocity that led to exchange, and from exchange to the polis–thereby drawing the entire astrologies of the Same into an abyss of dissimilarity" (2).30


M-M’ is this abyss. It is not time as time, but the specific modality of a time, which is unable to return to itself. The question is here that of the separation between use value and exchange value and of the fetishism that comes with it. The impossibility of the return is not the positive one due to consumption, for in this case a return of sort would still obtain. Rather, it is the totally negative lack of return which, as Marx says, "becomes madness" (269) — a madness which, however, constitutes the inner logic of capital.

5. The Labor of Fire

If capital is not labor, or if it is (and this only from the point of view of substance) only objectified labor, then what is labor? Labor as the not-capital is fundamentally two things. It is living labor and productive labor. I believe it is very important to distinguish between these concepts, for productive labor is always living labor, but living labor is not necessarily productive labor.

As Marx says in the already cited unpublished sixth chapter of Capital, "when we speak of productive labor we mean socially determined labor" (1977, 1043). However, I think this (of productive labor) remains the most problematic question in Marx’s critique of political economy. Marx equates living labor with productive labor. Of course, he does so because he looks at these categories from the point of view of capital in order to correct some mistakes of socialist writers, and, most importantly, because he wants to attack the uncritical view of some bourgeois political economists who say that all labor is productive (see, for instance, Marx 1973, 272–273). However, he himself creates some confusion because, at times, one gets the impression that there is no living labor over and beyond productive labor, whereas this is so only under capital; and this impression is dangerous because it is easily convertible into a dogma. Thus, it is important to keep in mind that for Marx it is precisely because labor, in and for itself, is not productive (or better neither productive nor unproductive), but creative, that it becomes productive or unproductive under capital. [31]

In other words, it is important to keep in mind that the category of productivity itself is a category of capital. Capital itself is "productive" (325); in its ability to go beyond its own limit, it is a revolutionary agent: "its production moves in contradictions which are constantly overcome but just as constantly posited" (410). Yet, let us warn those ‘leftists’ who too easily, whether arrogantly or surreptitiously, make a passage to an enthusiastic appreciation of this quality of capital (among these, the untimely and obnoxious preachers of the end of labor, the visionaries of dull paradises): Marx’s apparent enthusiasm ends here. He says: "The universality towards which it irresistibly strives encounters barriers in its own nature, which will, at a certain stage of its development, allow it to be recognized as being itself the greatest barrier to this tendency, and hence will drive towards its own suspension" (ibid). The end of productive and unproductive labor is the beginning of real creative labor, of real freedom; it is the lighting of a communal fire, and not the self-conceited absorption in a solipsistic desire.


But productive labor is not creative labor; rather, it is created labor, that is, posited by capital as necessary and surplus labor. Productive labor is value-preserving and value-increasing labor, and it is opposed to unproductive labor, which is however also living labor. Marx introduces the concept of productive labor as he analyzes the relation of capital to labor. Starting from the idea that the opposite of capital cannot be one particular commodity, for the substance of capital itself is the communal substance of all commodities, i.e., objectified labor, Marx says that the opposite of capital is then "labor which is still objectifying itself, labor as subjectivity" (272). Marx also expresses the difference between objectified and subjective labor as the difference between labor which is present in space and labor which is present in time. "If it is to be present in time, alive, then it can be present only as the living subject, in which it exists as capacity, as possibility; hence as worker" (272).

Of course, this is living labor, which is also said to be productive insofar as it is used by capital for its expansion or valorization. But it seems to me that the difference between productive and unproductive labor cannot be made on the basis of the description of labor as subjectivity or as presence in time. Thus, productive labor is only that labor which produces surplus value, i.e., unpaid labor; it is a form of living labor, but not the only one.

It is then important to see living labor as a category, not of political economy or capital, but of ontology. In fact, living labor is the "creative power" which, however, under capital, "comes to confront the worker as an alien power" (307). It is the subjectivity of which the worker divests himself. But living labor–and this needs to be stressed–is not only and not necessarily productive labor. The two coincide only when, as the result of the exchange between capital and labor, labor is transformed into capital (308). Marx also says: "The specific relationship between objectified and living labor that converts the former into capital also turns the latter into productive labor" (1977, 1043). Living labor is then called productive because it is in the production process that this transformation occurs. But labor becomes productive — in capital’s sense of the word — only because, fundamentally, it can produce — in the common sense of the word. In other words, labor is not an ontological, creative power because it is productive; rather, it becomes productive — and this is the only reason capital wants it — because it is an ontological, creative power. Without labor, capital would be nothing. But the opposite does not hold true. Without capital, labor would not be productive, and yet it would not be nothing, either. Then, what would it be?

For a logic (that of capital) which posits labor as either productive or unproductive, it seems that if it is not productive it must be unproductive. This is, at first sight, a logic of either/or which works quite well as far as the rhetoric of capital is concerned. However, at a closer examination, it reveals itself to be a logic of both/and generated by the contradictions of capital itself: "Capital, as the positing of surplus labor, is equally and in the same moment the positing and not-positing of necessary labor; it exists only in so far as necessary labor both exists and does not exist" (Marx 1973, 401).

But the positing and not-positing of necessary labor has nothing positive in it, for its positing is exploitation and its not-positing is annihilation. It is the double freedom which characterizes the worker’s existence (see Marx 1977, 272 and 874). Hence, contrary to those writers who tend to resolve difficulties by means of this logic32 both/and is not an alternative. In reality, the both/and modality enjoyed by the few is the condition for the neither/nor modality of a growing majority; both/and is a paradise whose presupposition and result is the tragedy of a neither/nor. Chiapas is an example of this. The possibility of a change does not reside in the acceptance of the both/and mentality but in the creation, out of a double negation, of a new radicality, one in which the having become of becoming is resurrected again to return to the immediacy of its subject. The logic which breaks that of capital is a logic of neither/nor, a logic of double negation, or, again, a logic of double resistance and absolute affirmation.33 Through this logic, labor returns to itself, not posited by capital as valorizing labor, but posited by itself as neither productive nor unproductive labor: as living labor or form-giving fire.

Productive labor, in fact, in its double aspect of value-preserving and value-creating labor, only makes sense within the logic of exchange value and money. In its first aspect, productive labor reproduces use value. As a form of living labor, it still gives form to things. But in its second aspect–that for which alone it is productive — it only creates exchange value, and the only thing to which it gives form is capital.

The abolition of productive labor is not simply the abolition of its second aspect, surplus labor. Even its first aspect, necessary labor, would cease to have to be conceived of in the way established by the logic of exchange value. In the same way in which Nietzsche’s abolition of the true world of ideas is also the abolition of this world as a world of appearances and thus the abolition of vulgar metaphysics as a whole, Marx’s theory of revolution implies the abolition not only of valorizing labor but also of the necessity of necessary labor as a necessity posited by capital. It is, in other words, the abolition of the concept of productive labor as a whole and of its counterpart, unproductive labor. It is also the abolition of the concept of waste labor. Neither-productive-nor-unproductive labor is labor which returns to itself as to its "immediate being" (1973, 308).34 It is however important to note that labor in its immediate being is not the in itself but the for itself of labor. The fact that under capital labor is not able to return to its immediacy is due to its being posited by capital as the essential moment in the mediation through which alone capital relates to its object. This object is, in the last analysis, the form of capital itself as more money and profit. It is the for itself of capital in search of independence, power, and identity.

Yet the power of capital is labor, which however becomes a power for capital only by ceasing to be a power for itself. In this sense labor too becomes the object of capital but only, of course, as labor alienated from the worker and confronting him as an alien power, indeed, as the power of capital itself.

The ability of capital to posit the necessity of labor as necessary labor, so that this positing is at the same time the positing of surplus labor, rests on its ability to create — through the circularity of production and consumption — a relentless system of need. Need is, in fact, "subsumable"35 and subsumed under capital. It is the vanishing mediation between production and consumption, that which posits both and is, in turn, posited by both. Living labor, which returns to itself as to its immediate being, is the exit from a system of need.36

In fact, the immediacy of labor is its freedom — not its double freedom, that is, the freedom of the modern workers who "neither form part of the means of production themselves..., nor do they own the means of production" (Marx 1977, 874) — but that which rests on the univocal disposition of its being. It is the freedom that destroys the both/and logic of capital to affirm itself as a new, absolute and radical essential difference.

As the negation of capital, this new essential difference is the abolition of money and exchange-value. It is not the abolition of labor, but the triumph of living, creative labor over a system of alienation and death. Labor that returns to its immediacy is labor that escapes the abyss and madness of capital. No longer divided into useful and abstract labor, no longer a vanishing mediation in the M-M’ process, this labor becomes the subject (i.e., the ground and agent) of a new determination of the concrete. It is in this sense that the Grundrisse is, as Negri says, a political work, for it presents a theory of radical subversion and revolution. As we have seen in the section on method in particular, there is, in the Grundrisse, a destruction of the petty logic of bourgeois political economy whereby capital is surreptitiously presented as an eternal element of production and relation of nature; but there is also a constructive dimension in it. This latter has to do with a new experience of time and labor — a time whose perfect tense is no longer the presupposition for the mortification of its becoming, but rather the ground from which becoming itself can attain the full recognition and status of being; and a labor which, freed from the law of value, is able to recuperate its self-identity and produce difference as difference, that is, not the difference which is measured by the universal equivalent form (the form of money), not, in other words, the quantitative difference that results in the price of the thing. It is rather the difference of each individuating expenditure of useful, creative labor: the moment which contracts all fire within itself, all being and all power.

In this sense, labor itself, in its self-identity and in its capacity to run throughout whatever, forming whatever without losing track of itself, is difference that creates difference. This labor comes into a direct, organic contact with the world, whose power it is. It destroys the old forms of time, the lines of history able only to cherish a dream and a destiny of death, to establish itself as the living, immediate form of freedom.

Notes

1. Cf. Kant (1929, for instance B225).

2. Benjamin (1969, 262).

3. Marx returns on this important point in the chapter on Capital: "If, then the specific form of capital is abstracted away, and only the content is emphasized, ..., then of course nothing is easier than to demonstrate that capital is a necessary condition for all human production. The proof of this proceeds precisely by abstraction from the specific aspects which make it the moment of a specifically developed historic stage of human production. The catch is that if all capital is objectified labor which serves as means for new production, it is not the case that all objectified labor which serves as means for new production is capital" (1973, 258).

4. "Labor...as the creator of useful value, as useful labor, is a condition of human existence which is independent of all forms of society; it is an eternal natural necessity which mediates the metabolism between man and nature, and therefore human life itself" (Marx 1977, 133).

5. I do not fully understand the real nature of abstract labor. My first persuasion was that abstract labor constituted the most common element of all useful labor. Indeed, this still seems to be correct from a logical and ontological point of view. However, this view would entail the presence of abstract labor before and beyond capital–a view that would be the opposite of what Marx says, for capital would be, again, necessary and eternal. Both Rubin (1972, 131-158) and Lukács (1971, 83-110; but particularly 87-88), among other writers, see abstract labor as pertaining exclusively to capital. In fact, abstract labor is the value-creating or value-increasing property of labor. Yet, precisely because of this, the following can be said: As a creator of value, abstract labor becomes the middle term in the dialectic between human beings and nature. It becomes the vanishing mediation between the object of capital and capital, and it appears as a power of capital. Outside capital, abstract labor would vanish in the return of labor to its immediacy. This does not mean that abstract labor would completely disappear. It only means that, for it to appear, certain historical and social conditions must obtain. Of course, this is another logical difficulty, for the question now becomes: Is then capital always possible? But I leave it at that for now. What I want to say is that, if abstract labor is–in Harvey’s apt expression–"a distillation...out of a seemingly infinite variety of concrete labor activities" (Harvey, 1989, 15; emphasis added), then it must somehow be there from the beginning. The point is that, under non-commodity production (production of use values)–and this would restore the correct historical perspective–there is simply no separation between the two aspects or properties of labor in question. The common element is then living labor before its division into useful and abstract labor. Consequently, the essential difference of capital is not simply abstract labor, but the separation of living labor into its two properties and the negation of its immediacy.

6. Capital reproduces abstract labor insofar as it "produces the worker as a wage-worker" (Marx, 1977, 716).


7. That permanence and becoming cannot exclude one another was already explained by Aristotle: "It is also evident that neither those who say that all things are at rest speak truly, nor those who say that all things are in motion . For if all things are at rest, whatever is true will always be true and whatever is false will always be false, yet there appears to be a change; ...And if all things are in motion , nothing will be true, and so everything will be false; but this [is]... impossible" (1979, 1012b 23-28).


8. Even though I agree with Negri’s characterization of the Grundrisse as an open work, I do not see why Capital — and this, of course, beyond the use that may have been made of it — would necessarily "block" revolutionary subjective action.


9. In Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, Schumpeter says: "Marx retained his early love during the whole of his lifetime. He enjoyed certain formal analogies which may be found between his and Hegel’s argument. He liked to testify to his Hegelianism and to use Hegelian terminology. But this is all. Nowhere did he betray positive science to metaphysics" (1950, 9-10; quoted in Rosdolsky 1977, xii; emphasis mine).


10. Of course, ‘metaphysics’ is here used only in its vulgar sense. See Remark 2, below.

11. It is true that, as Negri says, "Marx’s score with Hegel was settled long before [at the time of the so-called Early Writings]; here [in the Grundrisse] it is only a question of going back to him in a critical and scientific manner" (1991a, 3; brackets added). Indeed, the critique of Hegel is not at all an aspect of the Grundrisse. Under attack here are the bourgeois political economists and the socialists, first of all Proudhon. It is the latter who appear as Hegelians. Now, if we ask what is the result of the concept of circularity, the answer is identity. And it is this concept of identity that Marx wants to smash. Speaking of the problem of production and consumption–within the wider context of the concept of production as a Hegelian totality in which production, distribution, exchange and consumption are only members, "distinctions within a unity" (Marx, 1973, 99)–Marx says: "Thereupon, nothing simpler for a Hegelian than to posit production and consumption as identical. And this has been done not only by socialist belletrists but by prosaic economists themselves, e.g. Say; in the form that when one looks at an entire people, its production is its consumption. Or, indeed, at humanity in the abstract" (93-94).

12. See Negri (1991a, 9 and 85-104)

13. Notwithstanding Negri’s denial of the dialectic in all its forms, he still retains — both in Marx Beyond Marx and in his later writings — a dialectic of antagonism as the motor of his concept of a constitutive ontology.

14. See, for instance, the lectures on "The Nature of Language" in On the Way to Language. For Heidegger, the time of poiesis, the poetic experience, "points to something thought-provoking and memorable with which thinking has been charged from the beginning, even though in a veiled manner" (Heidegger, 1971, 87).

15. The translation of passages from Negri (1992) is mine.

16. See Duns Scotus (1987) and Deleuze (1994).

17. See Negri (1991b) and (1992).

18. This latter case is explained by the law of the tendency of the profit rate to decline (cf. Negri 1991a, 100).

19. This is the question of the tendencies of capital. "It is its tendency, therefore, to create as much labor as possible; just as it is equally its tendency to reduce necessary labor to a minimum. It is therefore equally a tendency of capital to increase the laboring population, as well as constantly to posit a part of it as surplus population–population which is useless until such time as capital can utilize it" (Marx, 1973, 399).

20. On the other hand, Negri adds, "the concrete...seeks in abstraction its determination" (48: Negri’s emphasis), and this constitutes the process of tendency.

21. On the question of subsumption, see the important unpublished sixth chapter of Capital (Marx 1977, 1019–1038).

22. "Marx’s theory of crisis and its counteracting tendencies is the core of his critique of capitalist production. Contrary to the commonsense view that crisis may then sound the death-knell of capitalism, Marx held that crises were the condition of capitalist development" (Aronowitz 1981, 184).

23. The dialectic between becoming and having become is also treated by Marx, in the Grundrisse, in the section on the accumulation of capital (459-471). In this section, capital emerges into existence as the truth of being, namely, as the essence it has become (I am, of course, using Hegelian terminology). From this moment on, "it creates its own presuppositions, i.e. the possession of the real conditions of new values without exchange," which appear "not as conditions of its arising, but as results of its presence" (460; Marx’s emphasis). Insofar as capital is establishing its ground, we are still within the Hegelian circle (cf. Book II of The Science of Logic, "The Doctrine of Essence"). Yet the spiral movement of productive capital does not cancel the dialectic between becoming and having become. Here becoming appears as living, abstract labor which changes capital from a thing to a process. "Labor is the yeast thrown into it, which starts it fermenting" (298). In this process, labor is not only consumed but also objectified, i.e., from becoming it itself changes to a having become. Labor, as subjectivity, acts upon an object and modifies it. In so doing, "as a modification of the object, it modifies its own form and changes from activity to being" (300; emphasis added). In Capital, I, Marx says the same: "Labor has become bound up in its object: labor has been objectified, the object has been worked on. What on the side of the worker appeared in the form of unrest [Unruhe] now appears, on the side of the product, in the form of Being [Sein], as a fixed, immobile characteristic" (287; see also 296). The product is the coincidence and the neutral result of three moments: the material, the instrument, and labor. The whole process is one of productive consumption, indeed it is "consumption of consumption itself" (Marx 1973, 301). The "form-giving activity consumes the object and consumes itself, but it consumes the given form of the object only in order to posit it in a new objective form, and it consumes itself only in its subjective form as activity" (301).

24. Money is either identical with itself (M-M), or it is the form of a time of difference (M-M’).

25. The philosophical significance of money is that it represents within the practical world the most certain image and the clearest embodiment of the formula of all being, according to which things receive their meaning through each other, and have their being determined by their mutual relations" (Simmel 1990, 128-129).

26. This law is a function of the relation between constant and variable capital. Constant and variable capital are, from the point of view of the valorization process, what means of production and labor-power are from the point of view of the labor process, that is, respectively, the objective and subjective factors of capital (Marx, 1977, 317). According to this law, the greater the mass of objectified labor (i.e. constant capital) set in motion by living labor, the less is the surplus-value which capital is able to appropriate. In other words, the gradual growth of constant capital in relation to variable capital a direct result of the valorization process makes the appropriation of surplus-value progressively smaller, for less labor is able to produce a greater quantity of commodities. In volume 3 of Capital, Marx says that this law is "another expression for the progressive development of the social productivity of labor" (1967, 212), and he explains it as follows: "Since the mass of the employed living labor is continually on the decline as compared to the mass of materialized labor set in motion by it, i.e., to the productively consumed means of production, it follows that the portion of living labor, unpaid and congealed in surplus-value, must also be continually on the decrease compared to the amount of value represented by the invested total capital. Since the ratio of the mass of surplus-value to the value of the invested total capital forms the rate of profit, this rate must constantly fall" (213)

27. See section 1, above.

28. Money is the first concept of capital and the first form in which it appears. Capital starts from money which is and is not in circulation (253). Like all other commodities, money has the ability to step outside circulation. But differently from all other commodities, which by stepping out of circulation are consumed and destroyed, money acquires thereby an independent existence as "the non-substantial general form of wealth" (254).

29. This contradiction is also present in the exchange process between the capitalist and the worker. In Capital Marx says: "Capital cannot therefore arise from circulation, and it is equally impossible for it to arise apart from circulation. It must have its origin both in circulation and not in circulation" (I, 268). And: "This whole course of events, the transformation of money into capital, both takes place and does not take place in the sphere of circulation. It takes place in circulation because it is conditioned by the purchase of the labor-power in the market; it does not take place in circulation because what happens there is only an introduction to the valorization process, which is entirely confined to the sphere of production" (I, 302).

30. Éric Alliez, Capital Times. Tales from the Conquest of Time, trans. Georges Van Den Abbeele. Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press, 1996.

31. Under capital, "living labor itself appears as alien vis-à-vis living labor capacity, whose labor it is, whose own life’s expression it is, for it has been surrendered to capital in exchange for objectified labor, for the product of labor itself" (Marx 1973, 462).

32. For an example in philosophy, see Bernstein (1992, particularly 309-314).

33. It is, in Negri’s words, the power of self-valorization (Negri 1991a). However, Negri does not characterize it as a neither/nor logic.

34. "This transformation [of labor into capital] is posited only in the production process itself. Thus, the question whether capital is productive or not is absurd. Labor itself is productive only if absorbed into capital, where capital forms the basis of production, and where the capitalist is therefore in command of production." And: "Labor, such as it exists for itself in the worker in opposition to capital, that is, labor in its immediate being, separated from capital, is not productive" (308).

35. "The apogee of critical science resides in specifying the non-subsumable" (Aronowitz, 1981, 249), namely, the principle of hope or desire against need. "The counterlogic is...to define desire as that which goes beyond need and is unrecuperable by the prevailing structure" (Ibid.).

36. What is meant here is, of course, capital-commanded need.

[The Bibliography for this essay follows below.]